Tényleg nem létezik?
  • sublimiter
    #1249
    "Dehat Dirac is ezt mondta,"

    1951. Nagyon le van maradva a magyar forumozo kozosseg. Igaz, ez mar nem Lorentz-etere, hanem a Dirac-eter.

    http://www.mountainman.com.au/aether_8.htm
    Extracts from an article by Dirac, Nature, 1951, vol. 168, pp. 906-907

    "Physical knowledge has advanced much since 1905,
    notably by the arrival of quantum mechanics, and
    the situation [about the scientific plausibility
    of aether] has again changed. If one examines the
    question in the light of present-day knowledge,
    one finds that the aether is no longer ruled out
    by relativity, and good reasons can now be
    advanced for postulating an aether. . . .

    We can now see that we may very well have an aether,
    subject to quantum mechanics and conformable to
    relativity, provided we are willing to consider a
    perfect vacuum as an idealized state, not
    attainable in practice.

    From the experimental point of view there does not
    seem to be any objection to this. We must make
    some profound alterations to the theoretical idea
    of the vacuum. . . . Thus, with the new theory of
    electrodynamics we are rather forced to have an
    aether"


    From the following document, further quotations
    relating to Dirac (bolded) and the aether:

    http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001614/01/Open_or_Closed-preprint.pdf

    Open or Closed?
    Dirac, Heisenberg, and the relation
    between classical and quantum mechanics

    ========[quoted material]===========

    Among these [outstanding problems
    apart from renormalisation] he [Dirac]
    lists the following:

    One of the problems is . . . accounting
    for the number 137. Other problems are
    how to introduce the fundamental length
    to physics in some natural way, how to
    explain the ratios of the masses of the
    elementary particles and how to explain
    their other properties. I believe separate
    ideas will be needed to solve these
    distinct problems and that they will be
    solved one at a time through successive
    stages in the future evolution of physics.

    At this point I find myself in disagreement
    with most physicists. They are inclined to
    think one master idea will be discovered
    that will solve all these problems together.
    (Dirac 1963, p. 50)

    Clearly Heisenberg would be counted among
    those who believed these various problems
    needed to be solved all at once. One of
    Dirac's more surprising approaches to
    solving these problems involved
    reintroducing an aether.

    Once again, he took the key to solving
    a quantum problem to lie in the
    development of a more adequate classical
    theory. In 1951 he had developed yet
    another classical electrodynamics, one
    that required postulating a velocity field
    defined at all points of space-time.

    Dirac interpreted this velocity as the
    velocity of the aether relative to the
    Earth. He argued that such an aether could
    be rendered consistent with relativity
    theory as long as one subjected the aether
    velocity to the quantum uncertainty
    relations. In this way Dirac was able to
    recover the Lorentz invariance of his theory.

    When, in 1952, Leopold Infeld pointed out
    that one could accept all of the conclusions
    of Dirac's new electrodynamics without
    postulating an aether, Dirac responded as
    follows:

    "Infeld has shown how the field equations
    of my new electrodynamics can be written
    so as not to require an aether. This is not
    sufficient to make a complete dynamical
    theory. It is necessary to set up an action
    principle and to get a Hamiltonian formulation
    of the equations suitable for quantization
    purposes, and for this the aether velocity is
    required" (Dirac 1952).

    For Dirac, the Poisson bracket correspondence
    that he had discovered in 1925 provided an
    important link between classical and quantum
    mechanics. One can only take an advantage of
    this correspondence if one has a Hamiltonian
    version of the classical theory. Thus in his
    search for a new QED, his strategy was to
    develop an appropriate Hamiltonian version
    of classical electrodynamics, which could
    then be quantized.

    If this meant reintroducing an aether and
    absolute simultaneity, then he was willing
    to do this. This reinforces the fact that,
    for Dirac, even the most accepted and well-
    established parts of theories were open to
    future revision.

    When confronted with these same difficulties
    of QED, Heisenberg, by contrast,attempted to
    solve all of these problems at once by
    restricting himself to observables only
    -the same trick that had worked for him in
    1925. This approach led Heisenberg to abandon
    quantum field theory in favor of the S-matrix
    program.

    For Dirac, on the otherhand, agreement with
    experiments was not the final test of a theory.
    Regarding renormalization theory he writes,

    "Just because the results happen to be in agreement
    with observation does not prove that one's
    theory is correct" (Dirac 1987, p. 196).